Page 61 - DPOL201_WESTERN_POLITICAL_THOUGHT_ENGLISH
P. 61

Unit 4: Aristotle’s Theory of Revolution


          While actual governments were bad, democratic government tended to be the best. Here again he  Notes
          described four kinds of democracy, which follow a progression from a moderate to an extreme
          one. Moderate democracy had some sort of property qualifications for officials, with the majority
          of people being agricultural and unmindful of political offices. The second type was similar to the
          first one, but without property qualifications for officials and granting everyone the right to hold
          office as long as they were not disqualified by birth. There would be no payment for performance
          of public duties, and government was governed in accordance with law. In the third kind, citizenship
          qualifications were relaxed to include all freemen, including aliens and children of emancipated
          slaves, who were excluded from the first two types. In an extreme democracy, all restraints were
          removed, being totally lawless with full rights to demagogues.
          In Aristotle, there was hardly a discussion of the ideal type except sketchy details, but a concern
          with the best practicable state, pointing out that a monarchy and aristocracy were best suited for
          ideal forms of state, since goodness was their aim. Moreover, monarchy of the ideal type was
          suited to domestic rather than political rule. Aristotle believed that politics, like all arts and
          sciences, had to not only consider the ideal constitution, but also know what was practicable and
          enduring under the given circumstances. In considering the feasibility of a constitution, Aristotle
          took into account the virtue and intelligence that an average individual possessed:
               The whole bent and bias of his thought must be toward the view that the ideal while
               conceded to be an effective force, must still be a force within the actual current of
               affairs and not dead against it... . The ideal state represented a conception of political
               philosophy which he inherited from Plato and which was in fact little congenial to his
               genius. The more he struck out an independent line of thought and investigation, the
               more he turned towards the analysis and description of actual constitutions. The great
               collection of one hundred and fifty eight constitutional histories made by him and his
               students marks the turning point in his thought and suggested a broader conception
               of political theory. This did not mean that Aristotle turned to description alone. The
               essence of the new conception was the uniting of empirical investigation with the
               more speculative consideration of political ideals. Moral ideals—the sovereignty of
               law, the freedom and equality of citizens, constitutional government, the perfecting of
               men in a civilized life—are always for Aristotle the ends for which the state ought to
               exist, what he discovered was that these ideals were infinitely complicated in the
               realization and required infinite adjustments to the conditions of actual government.
               Ideals must exist not like Plato’s pattern in the Heavens but as forces working in and
               through agencies by no means ideal.
          Plato classified governments on the basis of their law-abidingness, while Aristotle used the criterion
          of general welfare and the number who wielded political power. For Aristotle, “there are two
          distinct claims to power, one based upon the rights of property and the other upon the welfare of
          the greater number of human beings”. The correction to Plato’s formal classification enabled
          Aristotle to consider the justifiable claims to power in a state by adjusting and accommodating all
          claimants. He did not question Plato’s proposition that wisdom and virtue had an absolute claim
          to power, and tried to make it operative in practice. For Aristotle, a state ought to realize justice in
          its fullest and largest sense, for justice meant equality.
          Aristotle granted an absolute moral claim to power to those who possessed wealth, for the state
          was not a trading company or a contract. He rejected Plato’s solution of community of property as
          disastrous, and pointed out that there was not much of a difference between a plundering democracy
          and an exploitative oligarchy. However, he thought it unrealistic and unwise not to protect property,
          since property guaranteed good birth, sound education, reasonable associations and leisure. While
          the proprietied had an important claim to political power, equally convincing was the argument
          of democrats that numbers did matter. Aristotle concluded that no class had an absolute claim to


                                           LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY                                        55
   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66