Page 55 - DENG501_LITERARY_CRITICISM_AND_THEORIES
P. 55

Unit 4: Aristotle: The Poetics: Ideal Tragic Hero, Comedy



        depravity, but because of Hamartia or “miscalculation” on his part. Hamartia is not a moral failing,  Notes
        and hence it is unfortunate that it has been translated rather loosely as, “tragic flaw” as has been
        done by Bradley. Aristotle himself distinguishes hamartia from moral failing, and makes it quite
        clear that he means by it some error of judgment. He writes that the cause of the hero’s fall must
        lie, “not in depravity, but in some error or Hamartia on his part.” Butcher, Bywater and Rostangi,
        all agree that “Hamartia” is not a moral state; but an error of judgment which a man makes or
        commits. However, as Humphrey House tells us, Aristotle does not assert or deny anything about
        the connection of  hamartia with moral failings in the hero. “It may be accompanied by normal
        imperfection, but it is not itself a moral imperfection, and in the purest tragic situation the suffering hero is
        not morally to blame.”
        Hamartia : Its Three Sources
        Thus Hamartia is an error or miscalculation, but the error may arise in three ways. It may arise
        from “ignorance of some material fact or circumstance”, or secondly, it may be an error arising
        from hasty or careless view of the special case, or, thirdly, it may be an error voluntary, but not
        deliberate, as in the case of acts committed in anger or passion. Else and Martin Ostwald, both
        critics of eminence, interpret Hamartia actively and say that the hero has a tendency to err, created
        by lack of knowledge, and he may commit a series of errors. They further say that the tendency to
        err characterises the hero from the beginning—(it is a character-trait)—and that at the crisis of the
        play, it is complemented by the recognition scene (Anagnorisis), which is a sudden change, “from
        ignorance to knowledge”.
        Hamartia : Its Real Meaning and Significance
        As a matter of fact, Hamartia is a word which admits of various shades of meaning, and hence it
        has been differently inter-preted by different critics. However, all serious modern Aristotelian
        scholarship is agreed that Hamartia is not moral imperfection— though it may be allied with moral
        faults—that it is an error of judgment, whether arising from ignorance of some material
        circumstance, or from rashness and impulsiveness of temper, or from some passion. It may even
        be a character-trait, for the hero may have a tendency to commit errors of judgment, and may
        commit not one, but a series of errors. This last conclusion is borne out by the play  Oedipus
        Tyrannus to which Aristotle refers again and again, and which may be taken to be his ideal. In this
        play, the life of the hero is a chain of errors, the most fatal of all being his marriage with his
        mother. If King Oedipus is Aristotle’s ideal hero, we can say with Butcher that, “his conception of
        Hamartia includes all the three meanings mentioned above, which in English cannot be covered by a single
        term.” Hamartia is an error, or a series of errors, ‘Whether morally culpable or not,” committed by
        an otherwise noble person, and these errors derive him to his doom. The tragic irony lies in the
        fact that hero may err innocently, unknowingly, without any evil intention at all, yet he is doomed
        no less than those who are depraved and sin consciously. He has hamartia, he commits error or
        errors, and as a result his very virtues hurry him to his ruin. Says Butcher, “Othello in the modern
        drama, Oedipus in the ancient, are the two most conspicuous examples of ruin wrought by
        characters, noble, indeed, but not without defects, acting in the dark and, as it seemed, for the
        best.”
        The Ideal Hero : His Eminence
        Aristotle lays down another qualification for the tragic hero. He must be, “of the number of those
        in the enjoyment of great reputation and prosperity”. In other words, he must be a person who
        occupies a position of lofty eminence in society. He must be a highly placed individual, well
        reputed. This is so because Greek tragedy, with which alone Aristotle was familiar, was written
        about a few distinguished, royal families. Aristotle, basing his qualification of the tragic hero on
        what he was familiar with, considers eminence as essential for the tragic hero. Modern drama,
        however, has demonstrated that the meanest individual can serve as a tragic hero as well as a
        prince of the blood royal, and that tragedies of Sophoclean grandeur can be enacted even in
        remote country solitudes.



                                         LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY                                        49
   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60