Page 167 - DENG502_PROSE
P. 167

Unit 16:  Hazlitt--On Genius and Common Sense...


          the enjoyment of a first and deep passion, than in becoming the wife of some brother in iniquity  Notes
          to whom her pirating father would have trucked her for lucre?
          The ironic cadences of that last sentence cut to the bone, not merely as wit but as incisive criticism
          of social sickness in his age. Hunt interprets Byron more deeply perhaps than Byron intended. In
          a sense, Hunt extends Byron’s poem to a level of application that the apparent levity and flippancy
          of Byron’s tone might not otherwise reach with the general reader. Hunt reveals in Byron that
          which Byron’s tone might have concealed. Finally, the concluding paragraph of Hunt’s review is
          surely an example of tact andfinesse yielding “the prophetic spirit of common sense.” It is short,
          but to students of romanticism it cannot but suggest the struggles of Los with Vala in The Four Zoas
          or of Los with his Spectre in Jerusalem, which Blake was working out at the very time Hunt was
          writing. Here is the paragraph. The fact is, at the bottom of all these questions, that many things
          are made vicious, which are not so by nature; and many things made virtuous, which are only so
          by calling and agreement: and it is on the horns of this self-created dilemma, that society is
          continually writhing and getting desperate.
          For another exhibit of Leigh Hunt’s role as romantic critic, let us turn to his only extended effort
          at theoretical exposition, the essay “What Is Poetry?” which opens the 1844 volume Imagination
          and Fancy. This essay has been most severely — and strangely — denigrated by scholars in the
          past quarter century. The negative estimates concerning Hunt’s intelligence and critical achievement
          quoted at the beginning of this discussion are directed mainly at the 1844 essay. The essay has
          received more mockery than sympathetic reading in recent years. Ernest Bernbaum in 1929 called
          it “one of the clearest and most comprehensive, though not the profoundest, treatment of the
          subject by any of the Romantics.”  But M. H. Abrams wittily set the tone for contemporary reception
          of the essay by reminding his readers of a critical joke made at Hunt’s expense in the previous
          century. After summarizing differences between Coleridge, Hazlitt, Shelley, and Byron in the
          definition of poetry, Abrams quips, “Finally Leigh Hunt reconciled these differences by the simple
          device of a definition which, as David Masson has remarked, is ‘constructed on the principle of
          omitting nothing that anyone would like to see included’. “
          It seems to have been the elaborateness of Hunt’s opening definition that has led his detractors to
          deny him judgment or distinction of mind. Yet it seems to me that if one reads his opening
          paragraph, keeping in mind the relevant background of Hazlitt, Shelley, and the other great
          critical geniuses of the era, one may well be enlightened, pleased, and indeed impressed by the
          distinguished qualities of mind revealed. Hunt gives an imaginatively integrated account of
          romantic poetic theory that begins with a lucid, tightly structured outline, that is developed with
          clarity and cogency, and that ends with a fruitful juxtaposition of passages from Milton, Coleridge,
          and Shelley, which resonate with new significance in the context he has prepared for them. Perhaps
          by 1844 the principles expressed are no longer revolutionary. But neither are Hunt’s intentions
          revolutionary. They are, rather, “to furnish such an account, in an essay, of the nature and
          requirements of poetry, as may enable readers in general to give an answer on those points to themselves
          and others” [Hunt’s emphasis] .
          Turning to the essay, one discovers that Masson’s and Abrams’s word is not precisely accurate.
          The paragraph in question is not a “definition” according to the meaning by which one expects a
          man of abstract thought to summarize a topic or concept broadly and memorably in a short pithy
          expression. Rather, Hunt’s paragraph is an announcement and outline of the aspects of his subject
          to be covered at length in the essay, all brought together in a connected, if full, statement of his
          intent (current academic rhetoricians call such a passage occurring at the beginning of an essay the
          thesis statement). Indeed Hunt’s 1844 essay might seem to lack the lightning flashes of genius
          used by the romantic essayists, but Hunt’s procedure ably organizes for the wider, though educated
          Victorian reading public the complex theories of the romantic innovators.  Here is the opening
          statement of “What Is Poetry?”



                                           LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY                                       161
   162   163   164   165   166   167   168   169   170   171   172