Page 153 - DPOL201_WESTERN_POLITICAL_THOUGHT_ENGLISH
P. 153

Unit 8: Jean Jacques Rousseau


              Rousseau’s political philosophy, by implication, according to Cobban, discussed the subject  Notes
              matter of the politics of the twentieth century, like the reality of nationalism, state sovereignty,
              the need for economic equality and the state’s role in realizing it, the bases of popular politics
              and the reconciliation of these with the principles of politics based on a rational, self-
              determining individual. Rousseau also pointed out the close relation-ship between liberty
              and equality, and the fact that without equality, liberty would be non-existent. He abandoned
              his initial hostility to property, and accepted it as an essential institution of society. Unlike
              Locke, he recognized how property could become an instrument of private domination,
              which was why property had to be controlled by the General Will. He considered property
              as being the root cause of moral corruption and injustice. Since industrial society was not yet
              an existing reality, he idealized a property-owning society where everyone would be equal
              and independent. In this he retained the Lockeian spirit.
              Liberty, for Rousseau, was the greatest good. Liberty was only possible when dependence
              between human beings was eliminated, if not at least regulated by law. He understood
              liberty as participation and popular sovereignty. It was for this reason that many see his
              philosophy as being compatible with collectivism, Jacobinism, despotism and totalitarianism.
              It was anti-Lockeian, for there was no effort to preserve the rights of the individual against
              the state (Vaughan 1962: 48). The Social Contract sounded the death-knell of individualism,
              which had held sway since the days of Locke.
              Rousseau’s theory was egalitarian, anti-hierarchical, republican and democratic. Like Locke
              and Montesquieu, he was critical of the nobility and benevolent despots and upheld the rule
              of law. Nobody (other than Rousseau) stressed the importance of community on the grounds
              that interdependence and cooperation enhanced the powers of human beings, and that
              socialization enabled them to acquire consciousness and rationality. However, he was not an
              unabashed supporter or admirer of modern society and civilization.
              Rousseau’s solution for the ills of society was not to beckon men to the woods, nor to
              advocate the destruction of all social inter-dependencies. He proposed, instead, paradox:  let
              us create a society which causes men to grow close to one another, to become so strongly
              solidary that each member will be made dependent on the whole society and, by that very
              fact, be released from personal dependencies.
              There was no denying the fact that Rousseau’s political philosophy was one of the most
              innovative, striking, remarkable, and brilliantly-argued theories. In the entire history of
              social and political ideas, there were only a few parallels to his edifice in its force of argument
              and passion for outlining a structure which was supposed to put an end to, most, if not all,
              human predicaments.
              His most spectacular achievement was that he understood the pivotal problem that faced
              individuals in society—how to reconcile individual interests with those of the larger interests
              of society. He tried to resolve this delicate problem in his own way, by depicting human
              nature in operation under the sway of an all-comprehensive political structure. The attempt
              by itself was highly laudable, as this was the most important problem that a political theorist
              faced, and in most cases the resolution was far from satisfactory.
              Rousseau’s influence has changed over the last three centuries. In the eighteenth century, he
              was seen as a critic of the status quo, challenging the concept of progress, the core of the
              Enlightenment belief-structure. In the nineteenth century, he was seen as the apostle of the
              French Revolution and the founder of the Romantic Movement. In the twentieth century, he
              has been hailed as the founder of the democratic tradition, while at the same time assailed
              for being the philosophical inspiration of totalitarianism. These indicate that it has not been
              possible to interpret Rousseau within a single framework of analysis.


                                           LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY                                       147
   148   149   150   151   152   153   154   155   156   157   158