Page 68 - DENG501_LITERARY_CRITICISM_AND_THEORIES
P. 68

Literary Criticism and Theories



                  Notes          in its "text." Indirect speech acts are ones in which the meaning lies outside the "text" but is
                                 understood by the hearer due to a shared contextual understanding with the speaker. In both
                                 cases the contextual understanding of the utterance is typically considered to be subject to "normal"
                                 circumstances. In other words, the hearer knows what the speaker is talking about, whether he
                                 uses direct or indirect language, because the utterance and its reception occur in a situation that
                                 lies in the realm of both parties' understanding. It is this idea of normal circumstances with which
                                 Fish takes issue. He says, " . . . I am making the same argument for 'normal context' that I have
                                 made for 'literal meaning' . . . There will always be a normal context, but it will not always be the
                                 same one". As an example he uses John Searle's use of the following situation:
                                 Searle begins by imagining a conversation between two students. Student X says, "Let's go to the
                                 movies tonight," and student Y replies, "I have to study for an exam." The first sentence, Searle
                                 declares, "constitutes a proposal in virtue of its meaning," but the second sentence, which is
                                 understood as a rejection of the proposal, is not so understood in virtue of its meaning because "in
                                 virtue of its meaning it is simply a statement about Y". It is here, in the assertion that either of these
                                 sentences is ever taken in the way it is "in virtue of its meaning," that this account must finally be
                                 attacked. For if this were the case, then we would have to say that there is something about the
                                 meaning of a sentence that makes it more available for some illocutionary uses than for others, and
                                 this is precisely what Searle proceeds to say about "I have to study for an exam": "Statements of this
                                 form do not, in general, constitute rejections of proposals, even in cases in which they are made in
                                 response to a proposal. Thus, if Y had said I have to eat popcorn tonight or I have to tie my shoes in
                                 a normal context, neither of these utterances would have been a rejection of the proposal" .
                                 At this point, Fish asks "Normal for whom?" in regards to Searle's proposed normal context. He
                                 then goes on to list a number of situations in which eating popcorn and tying shoes could be taken
                                 as a rejection of a proposal as long as both X and Y were privy to the circumstances. To the
                                 argument that these circumstances are special as opposed to normal, Fish answers that "'normal'
                                 is content specific and to speak of a normal context is to be either redundant (because whatever in
                                 a given context goes without saying is the normal) or to be incoherent (because it would refer to
                                 a context whose claim was not to be one)" . He does not intend to imply that an utterance can mean
                                 anything, but, rather, that its meaning is subject to certain constraints: " . . . chaos . . . would be
                                 possible only if a sentence could mean anything at all in the abstract." He goes on to point out,
                                 however, that "A sentence . . . is never in the abstract; it is always in a situation, and the situation
                                 will already have determined the purpose for which it can be used" .
                                 It is difficult to place Fish in relation to the other critics we have examined in class. He seems to be
                                 anti-structuralist, anti-formalist, and anti-stylist, yet he does not deny the validity of many of their
                                 premises, only the conclusions they derive from them. Essentially Fish's position seems to be
                                 composed of the ideas that
                                 1. reading is an activity,
                                 2. rather than being imbedded in formal features, the meaning of any text is brought to it by the
                                    reader's interpretive strategy,
                                 3. interpretive communities make it possible for there to be some agreement on the meanings of
                                    texts,
                                 4. all acts of interpretation occur in some context or other.
                                 These seem to be straightforward and even obvious assertions, yet they seem to frighten many
                                 critics. They apparently feel the same way that Wimsatt and Beardsley do, that Fish's method
                                 leads to a lack of certainty. Fish himself does not try to argue against this claim directly. In fact, at
                                 the end of Interpreting the Variorum he himself admits this uncertainty when discussing how one
                                 can know to which interpretive community one belongs. He says, "The answer is he can't, since
                                 any evidence brought forward to support the claim would itself be an interpretation . . ." All one
                                 can have as far as proof of membership is a " . . . nod of recognition from someone in the same
                                 community . . ." He ends this essay with the only words that someone who speaks from his
                                 viewpoint can truly maintain with any certainty: "I say it [we know] to you now, knowing full
                                 well that you will agree with me (that is, understand) only if you already agree with me" .



        62                               LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY
   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73