Page 71 - DENG501_LITERARY_CRITICISM_AND_THEORIES
P. 71

Unit 6: Is There a Text In This Class—Stanley Fish: Analysis



        (indeed, in the course of this essay I will be arguing that unintelligibility, in the strict or pure  Notes
        sense, is an impossibility), but that there are readers and hearers for whom the intelligibility of the
        question would have neither of the shapes it had, in a temporal succession, for my colleague. It is
        possible, for example, to imagine someone who would hear or intend the question as an inquiry
        about the location of an object, that is, "I think I left my text in this class; have you seen it?" We
        would then have an "Is there a text in this class?" and the possibility, feared by the defenders of the
        normative and determinate, of an endless succession in numbers, that is, of a world in which
        every utterance has an infinite plurality of meanings. But that is not what the example, however
        it might be extended, suggests at all. In any of the situations I have imagined (and in any that I
        might be able to imagine) the meaning of the utterance would be severely constrained, not after it
        was heard but in the ways in which it could, in the first place, be heard. An infinite plurality of
        meaning would be a fear only if sentences existed in a state in which they were not already
        embedded in, and had come into view as a function of some situation or other. That state, if it
        could be located, would be the normative one, and it would be disturbing indeed if the norm were
        free-floating and indeterminate.
        But there is no such state; sentences emerge only in situations, and within those situations, the
        normative meaning of an utterance will always be obvious or at least accessible, although within
        another situation that same utterance, no longer the same, will have another normative meaning
        that will be no less obvious and accessible. (My colleague's experience is precisely an illustration).
        This does not mean that there is no way to discriminate between the meanings an utterance ca
        have in different situations, but that the discrimination will already have been made by virtue of
        our being in a situation (we are never not in one) and that in another situation the discrimination
        will also have already been made, but differently. In other words, while at any one point it is
        always possible to order and rank "Is there a text in this class?" and "Is there a text in this class?"
        (because they will always have already been ranked), it will never be possible to give them an
        immutable once-and-for-all ranking, a ranking that is independent of their appearance or
        nonappearance in situations (because it is only in situations that they do or do riot appear).
        Nevertheless, there is a distinction to he made between the two that allows us to say that, in a
        limited sense, one is more normal than the other: for while each is perfectly normal in the context
        in which their literalness is immediately obvious (the successive contexts occupied by my colleague),
        as things stand now, one of those contexts is surely more available, and therefore more likely to be
        the perspective within which the utterance is heard, than the other. Indeed, we seem to have here
        an instance of what I would call "institutional nesting": If "Is there a text in this class?", is hearable
        only by those who know what is included under the rubric "first day of class," and if "Is there a
        text in this class?", is hearable only by those whose categories of understanding include the concerns
        of contemporary literary theory, then it is obvious that in a random population presented with the
        utterance, more people would "hear" "is there a text in this class?", than "Is there a text in this
        class?"; and, moreover, that while "Is there a text in this class?" could be immediately hearable by
        someone for whom "Is there a text in this class?" would have to be laboriously explained, it is
        difficult to imagine someone capable of hearing "Is there a text in this class?" who was not already
        capable of hearing "Is there a text in this class." (One is hearable by anyone in the profession and
        by most students and by many workers in the book trade, and the other in the profession who
        would not think it peculiar to find, as I did recently, a critic referring to a phrase "made popular
        by Lacan."). To admit as much is not to weaken my argument by reinstating the category of the
        normal, because the category as it appears in that argument is not transcendental but institutional;
        and while no institution is so universally in force and so perdurable that the meanings it enables
        will be normal for ever, some institutions or forms of life are so widely lived in that for a great
        many people the meaning they enable seem "naturally" available and it takes a special effort to see
        that they are products of circumstances.
        The point is an important one, because it accounts for the success with which an Abrams or an
        E. D. Hirsch can appeal to a shared understanding of ordinary language and argue from that
        understanding to the availability of a core of determinate meanings. When Hirsch offers "The air
        is crisp" as an example of a "verbal meaning" that is accessible to all speakers of the language, and



                                         LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY                                        65
   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76