Page 194 - DENG502_PROSE
P. 194

Prose


                    Notes          ordinary propositions about objects, causal relations, the self, and so on, are semantically equivalent
                                   to propositions about one’s experiences.
                                   Many commentators have since rejected this understanding of Humean empiricism, stressing an
                                   epistemological, rather than a  semantic reading of his project. According to this view, Hume’s
                                   empiricism consisted in the idea that it is our knowledge, and not our ability to conceive, that is
                                   restricted to what can be experienced. To be sure, Hume thought that we can form beliefs about
                                   that which extends beyond any possible experience, through the operation of faculties such as
                                   custom and the imagination, but he was skeptical about claims to knowledge on this basis.
                                   Induction
                                   Few philosophers are as associated with induction as David Hume; but Hume himself rarely used
                                   the term and when he did, he used it to support a point he was arguing. He made no indication
                                   that he saw any problem with induction. Induction became associated with Hume only in the
                                   early twentieth century; John Maynard Keynes may have been the first to draw the connection.
                                   The connection is now standard, but is based on what current scholars mean by “induction”, not
                                   how Hume used the term in his writings.
                                   The cornerstone of Hume’s epistemology is the problem of induction. This may be the area of
                                   Hume’s thought where his scepticism about human powers of reason is most pronounced.
                                   Understanding the problem of induction is central to grasping Hume’s philosophical system.
                                   The problem concerns the explanation of how we are able to make inductive inferences. Inductive
                                   inference is reasoning from the observed behaviour of objects to their behaviour when unobserved;
                                   as Hume says, it is a question of how things behave when they go “beyond the present testimony
                                   of the senses, and the records of our memory”. Hume notices that we tend to believe that things
                                   behave in a regular manner; i.e., that patterns in the behaviour of objects will persist into the
                                   future, and throughout the unobserved present. This persistence of regularities is sometimes called
                                   Uniformitarianism or the Principle of the Uniformity of Nature.
                                   Hume’s argument is that we cannot rationally justify the claim that nature will continue to be
                                   uniform, as justification comes in only two varieties, and both of these are inadequate. The two
                                   sorts are: (1) demonstrative reasoning, and (2) probable reasoning. With regard to (1), Hume
                                   argues that the uniformity principle cannot be demonstrated, as it is “consistent and conceivable”
                                   that nature might stop being regular. Turning to (2), Hume argues that we cannot hold that nature
                                   will continue to be uniform because it has been in the past, as this is using the very sort of
                                   reasoning (induction) that is under question: it would be  circular reasoning. Thus no form of

                                   justification will rationally warrant our inductive inferences.
                                   Hume’s solution to this problem is to argue that, rather than reason, natural instinct explains the
                                   human ability to make inductive inferences. He asserts that “Nature, by an absolute and
                                   uncontroulable [sic] necessity has determin’d us to judge as well as to breathe and feel”. Although
                                   many modern commentators have demurred from Hume’s solution, some have notably concurred
                                   with it, seeing his analysis of our epistemic predicament as a major contribution to the theory of
                                   knowledge. For example, philosopher John D. Kenyon writes:
                                   Reason might manage to raise a doubt about the truth of a conclusion of natural inductive inference
                                   just for a moment in the study, but the forces of nature will soon overcome that artificial skepticism,
                                   and the sheer agreeableness of animal faith will protect us from excessive caution and sterile
                                   suspension of belief.
                                   Causation
                                   The notion of  causation is closely linked to the problem of induction. According to Hume, we
                                   reason inductively by associating constantly conjoined events, and it is the mental act of association
                                   that is the basis of our concept of causation. There are three main interpretations of Hume’s theory



          188                              LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY
   189   190   191   192   193   194   195   196   197   198   199