Page 29 - DPOL202_COMPARATIVE_POLITICS_AND_GOVERNMENT_ENGLISH
P. 29

Comparative Politics and Government


                    Notes             variables and relates these to each other. As in the case of the method of difference, all other
                                      factors must be kept constant; in Mill’s words, “that we may be warranted in inferring causation
                                      from concomitance of variations, the concomitance itself must be proved by the Method of
                                      Difference.”
                                      Mill’s method of concomitant variations is often claimed to be the first systematic formulation
                                      of the modern comparative method. It should be pointed out, however, that Mill himself
                                      thought that the methods of difference and of concomitant variations could not be applied in
                                      the social sciences because sufficiently similar cases could not be found. He stated that their
                                      application in political science was “completely out of the question” and branded any attempt
                                      to do so as a “gross misconception of the mode of investigation proper to political phenomena.”
                                      Durkheim agreed with Mill’s negative judgment: “The absolute elimination of adventitious
                                      elements is an ideal which can not really be attained; . . . one can never be even approximately
                                      certain that two societies agree or differ in all respects save one.” These objections are founded
                                      on a too exacting scientific standard—what Sartori calls “over-conscious thinking.” It is important
                                      to remember, however, that in looking for comparable cases, this standard should be
                                      approximated as closely as possible.
                                      The area approach appears to lend itself quite well to this way of applying the comparative
                                      method because of the cluster of characteristics that areas tend to have in common and that can,
                                      therefore be used as controls. But opinions on the utility of the area approach differ sharply:
                                      Gunnar Heckscher states that “area studies are of the very essence of comparative government,”
                                      and points out that “the number of variables, while frequently still very large, is at least
                                      reduced in the case of a happy choice of area.” Roy C. Macridis and Richard Cox also argue
                                      that if areas are characterized by political as well as non-political uniformities, “the area concept
                                      will be of great value, since certain political processes will be compared between units within
                                      the area against a common background of similar trait configuration”; they cite Latin America
                                      as an example of an area offering the prospect of “fruitful intra– area comparison.” On the
                                      other hand, Dank-wart A. Rustow declares in a recent article that area study is “almost obsolete,”
                                      and he shows little faith in it as a setting for “manageable comparative study.” He argues that
                                      “mere geographic proximity does not necessarily furnish the best basis of comparison,” and
                                      furthermore that “comparability is a quality that is not inherent in any given set of objects;
                                      rather it is a quality imparted to them by the observer’s perspective.” This is a compelling
                                      argument that should be carefully considered.
                                      It is not true that areas reflect merely geographic proximity; they tend to be similar in many
                                      other basic respects. By means of an inductive process—a factor analysis of 54 social and
                                      cultural variables on 82 countries—Bruce M. Russett discovered socio-culturally similar
                                      groupings of countries, which correspond closely to areas or regions of the world as usually
                                      defined. Comparability is indeed not inherent in any given area, but it is more likely within an
                                      area than in a randomly selected set of countries. It seems unwise, therefore, to give up the area
                                      approach in comparative politics. But two important provisos should be attached to this
                                      conclusion. First, the area approach can contribute to comparative politics if it is an aid to the
                                      comparative method, not if it becomes an end in itself. Otherwise, area study may indeed
                                      become “a form of imprisonment.” It is against this danger that the thrust of Rustow’s argument
                                      is directed. Second, the area approach should not be used indiscriminately, but only where it
                                      offers the possibility of establishing crucial controls. In this respect, some of the smaller areas
                                      may offer more advantages than the larger ones—Scandinavia, for example, which has barely
                                      been exploited in this manner, or the Anglo-American countries, which have received greater
                                      comparative attention (but which do not constitute an area in the literal sense).
                                      An alternative way of maximizing comparability is to analyze a single country diachronically.
                                      Such comparison of the same unit at different times generally offers a better solution to the
                                      control problem than comparison of two or more different but similar units (e.g., within the
                                      same area) at the same time, although the control can never be perfect; the same country is not
                                      really the same at different times. A good example of diachronic comparative analysis is Charles
                                      E. Frye’s study of the empirical relationships among the party system, the interest group


          24                               LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY
   24   25   26   27   28   29   30   31   32   33   34