Page 97 - DPOL201_WESTERN_POLITICAL_THOUGHT_ENGLISH
P. 97

Unit 6: Thomas Hobbes


          nature”. Then he recombined these elements into a new body politic, the Leviathan. Hobbes  Notes
          compared his method to taking apart a watch or a small engine in order to know its constituent
          parts.
          Hobbes contended that the aim of all philosophy was to give a mechanical theory of the universe.
          This was seen as a problem in geometry. Atoms had no properties of their own, except when seen
          as a part of certain laws of motion. Matter was in a state of perpetual motion. The problem was
          how it moved from one state of motion to another. The human being was also an automaton, for
          all his actions could be explained by the laws of motion. All motions originated, and were with
          reference to, the human body. It would function harmoniously with minimum friction, like a wrist
          watch, if arranged properly. If not, then the parts would destroy one another.
          Hobbes’s  mechanical materialism differed from Marx’s  dialectical materialism. A mechanical
          materialist perceived matter to be passive, with change stimulated from the external environment.
          A dialectical materialist regarded matter as being active, changing from within without much help
          from the environment. The mechanistic conception implied that the whole was no more than a
          sum total of the parts that comprised it. The whole was not more important or greater than the
          constituent parts. Applying the analogy to the state, Hobbes viewed the state as an aggregate and
          not a compound of individuals.
          Thus, the ultimate aim of Hobbes, as of Galileo, was to use the mathematical framework to describe
          a physical and political phenomenon, as mathematics provided unity, certainty and precision.
          Following Galileo, he opposed the Aristotelian idea of things moving towards some goal, and
          then coming to rest. On the contrary, things in motion tended to stay that way. Philosophy, for
          Hobbes, was strictly utilitarian and practical— a knowledge of the effects which could be produced
          by a given set of causes, or conversely, of causes that resulted in a set of effects. Like Bacon and
          Hamilton, he regarded power as the end of knowledge and an instrument to harness the forces of
          nature. All individuals were equal, but differences arose due to their differing capacity for
          knowledge. All knew that war and civil strife were the worst possible calamities, but few understood
          their causes and the ways to avoid them. Very few could comprehend the means by which peace
          could be maintained.
          Hobbes insisted that if science had to gain ascendancy, it would have to receive support from
          certain sections in society. He emphasized that philosophy and science could only flourish in an
          affluent society, and cited the examples of Athens and Rome. He cautioned against the pursuit of
          wealth as an overwhelming goal, for if that happened, it would subordinate knowledge, increase
          corruption, imperil peace and safety in civil society. England of the seventeenth century was
          similar to Athens. In both societies, philosophy was no longer pursued for the knowledge and the
          truth it bestowed, but was seen as a means to earning a living. The political message that he
          conveyed was that it would be fatal to rely on the advice of those who were more dextrous with
          making money rather than knowledge.

          6.3 Hobbes’ Political Philosophy
          Hobbes stress was on fear and self-interest as the two fundamental human motivations which
          needed to be tempered and controlled by an omnipotent sovereign power. The presence of a
          sovereign separated a state of nature from a political society. Using the device of the social contract,
          Hobbes explained the nature of sovereignty, its location, the relationship with the individual, the
          essential functions of a government, and the origins of a state. Hobbes defended a case for absolute
          legal sovereignty, since sovereign power was the result of a zero-sum game. Absolute power
          ensured complete order. Conversely, its absence meant chaos.
          In view of the fact that the English Parliament succeeded in extracting a Petition of Rights from
          Charles I, Hobbes warned his readers through his translation of Thucydides (1628) against any


                                           LOVELY PROFESSIONAL UNIVERSITY                                        91
   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102